Corporations and Their Stakeholders: The U.S. Business School Contribution to Socialist Indoctrination

One hears frequently of the leftist indoctrination of college students in the United States, whose recruitment to the ranks of progressives and, more recently, socialists is apparent. Opinion polls show the approval of socialism among millennials at just over 50% in 2019. 

I presume that in the liberal arts and humanities this indoctrination occurs in history, political science and related classes somewhat systematically, and in other courses by random observations of socialist professors. In the case of business students, I am fully aware of the indoctrination process, having taught for many years in business schools.

For many years I assumed that the exposure to economics in college and having been the victims of regulatory measures once they begin careers in business, businessmen would be natural advocates of laissez-faire capitalism and the market system. With the introduction of systematic indoctrination in business schools, however, one can find all sorts of indoctrinated socialists in business and, perhaps especially, in financial firms. This essay will address the nature of the indoctrination of business students.


Universities endow students with access to business careers. First, they seek to indoctrinate them.

The corporation has always been vilified by its socialist detractors – those who ignore the fact that corporations are the producers of the goods we consume and the provider of jobs. They are the institution that develops and applies new technologies, and gives us investment opportunities for our 401K plans. But according to “stakeholder theorists,”  who provide systematic indoctrination of our future business leaders, the corporation has the potential for doing some good, but only if academics train students to overcome the corporation’s history of evils and abuses.

Future managers must be coached to be ethical, which means to be socially minded. Serve the corporate stakeholder!

Stakeholder advocates teach that those in society who understand ethics and proper managerial behavior, must transform corporations into socially responsible institutions which do not just show concern for the stock-holding owners of corporations and their profits. No, they must consider and respond to the needs and desires of all the groups and organizations which are negatively affected by the functioning of corporations.  All such groups who have a stake in the outcomes of corporate activity – corporate “stakeholders” – must be part of corporate leaders’ concerns.

Competent and ethical students take a “social” view of the firm and its “abuses.” Social is sometimes a code word for socialism.

Moderate stakeholder theorists, if I may use a distinction made by a stakeholder theorist among my business school colleagues, are simply individuals who wish to teach ethics to prospective managers. The more radical among business school faculty, however, advocate more forceful methods of imposing stakeholder principles on corporations. This more radical type of stakeholder advocate hopes to impact the functioning of corporations by applying “social controls” to corporate management. Some might be willing to be satisfied with teaching corporate leaders their corporate social responsibility (CSR), but others would like to take further, more extreme measures to make sure that CEOs rigorously apply the stakeholder principles they learned as undergraduates.

One might notice the asymmetry of stakeholder theory. On one side of the coin, all corporate activity imposes external costs on society. Those thus impacted are thought to have a claim on the corporation for compensating benefits. But note that corporations produce both costs and benefits for society. For example, corporations pay taxes and perform other positive functions and produce positive externalities. On the other side of the coin, perhaps those who benefit from the existence of a given corporation should be considered “beneficiaries”, rather than “stakeholders”, and beneficiaries should provide revenues in some form for their beneficiary social responsibility (BSR), which would be remitted to all socially acceptable corporations. The reader should not expect ever to hear such a proposal in real life, but it is no less unreasonable than the stakeholder notion.

Those corporations performing helpful social functions, such as would bring happiness to any state chosen to be the headquarters of such a corporation, should probably also have an agent serve in the upper echelons of the tax administration of such states, if not in the IRS in Washington, D.C. This tongue-in-cheek proposal, of course, will not attract any positive response from socialists (“stakeholder theorists”) in our business schools.

It is hardly difficult to find persuasive refutation of stakeholder claims from the perspective of economics. According to stakeholder advocates, their objective is to make “values” necessarily and explicitly a part of doing business. Managers are to be indoctrinated and trained to share the wealth the corporation creates with their core stakeholders.

Socially competent managers accept social values and try to appease all stakeholders.

“The Corporate Objective,” the highest stakeholder value, is that “truth and freedom are best served by seeing business and ethics as connected.” The notion of intervening in private commerce to achieve social justice originated, of course, in the public sector. Stakeholder advocacy merely extends the process to the private sector. We are accustomed to perceiving the public sector in terms of politics and political action. Aside from the public corporation, only governments – federal, state, and local – can generate resources on a large scale. In a sense governments also have shareholders, citizens who pay taxes and provide services such as voting and volunteering for public projects. Strictly speaking, we do not separate ownership and non-ownership in governance, since the founders perceived an equal creation of all the governed. Those not in a position to contribute to the generation of wealth, however, are akin to the stakeholders of governments. They are franchised to use the public infrastructure, receive subsidies, enjoy public health services, educational programs, and so on. Legislatures have recognized their entitlement, which is by community agreement separated from ownership.

Stakeholder theory comes along much later and places its focus on the private sector, advocating an expansion of the services received by private stakeholders and demanding increasing private provision for their needs and claims. But those needs and claims are more clearly the business of the public sector. Society as a whole, in the form of representative government, agrees to expand the benefits of legitimate stakeholders – low income recipients, the poorly educated, the physically handicapped or chronically ill, and others unable to provide for themselves. This is done to express the community’s preferences for justice and equity and includes taxation of the private sector to secure the essential welfare funds.

Marx and Lenin were convinced both government and industry should provide welfare and redistribute income.

Market advocates have long held that more efficient and effective care of social stakeholders would occur if the private sector were concerned strictly with taking care of the ownership and allocation of private resources. If returns are maximized and efficiency prevails in the private sector, large amounts of resources are generated for tax purposes and the redistribution of funds through the public sector. Moreover, as we learned from the socialist experience in the Soviet Union and East Europe, the generation of public resources is not unrelated to the state of private incentives. If the provision of resources is taken over completely by the state, the resultant incentive incompatibilities guarantee a much diminished national product, much reduced taxation flows, and a much lower level of living in general.

The socialization of the private sector is not an efficient way to generate resources for the underprivileged. Teaching prospective managers that they may consider themselves the “owners” of the corporation’s resources (because they need no longer feel any responsibility to the shareholders, who are the actual owners of the property) and that those resources should be used for social claims is certainly a poor idea from the standpoint of justice or efficient resource allocation. Although managers may engage in moral hazard (using resources in their personal interest, in this case to enhance the position of stakeholders, far and near, rather than create wealth for the firm’s owners), this diversion from efficient management will lead them into unproductive pursuits that shrink the capacity for wealth creation. This diversion of resources from the owners by the shareholders, imposes upon owners one more set of redistribution demands through a form of private or “quasi” taxation. And this is performed in the name of ethics?

Stakeholdler advocates are apparently unwilling to perceive that business activity already takes place in a world in which there are numerous laws and regulations on corporations to account for social interests. Calling on business leaders to impose additional, self-administered measures to enhance additional income redistribution at the expense of the firm’s owners can only be the result of over-reach. Thus, Milton Friedman, the Nobel prize-winning economist famous for his advocacy of economic freedoms, is quoted as saying that stakeholder advocates are “preaching pure and unadulterated socialism.”

Stakeholder advocates rely on sweeping generalizations about the fiduciary and social obligations of corporations. They promote the notion that any individual or organization that “invests” in corporations has the right to some return on the investment, i.e., to some of the fruits of the firm’s productivity. They do not usually elaborate on the idea of what kind of return they might expect from their “investment,” the nature of which is likewise vague. In the current economy, one may rest assured that if any individual or organization has a claim on any specific firm for any specific “investment,” the demand for such a return will already have been pressed in the courts. In any case, all the stakeholders in American corporations having a legitimate claim on a return are already receiving it.

With monopoly power a firm can restrict output, raise the price, and contribute more to stakeholder causes.

It has occurred to some theorists that stakeholder-oriented companies possessing any monopoly power have lower output and higher prices. Firms in this situation may choose voluntarily to be stakeholder-oriented, because they are in a position to charge higher prices. That benefits stakeholders because higher prices are required for firms of this type to produce greater revenues not only to cover current costs and make a “normal” profit, but also to generate additional revenues for stakeholder causes.

We need not pursue the analysis of a government tax imposed on an imperfectly competitive firm here. The government already taxes such firms to finance the usual social programs. This tax, generally of the excise type, will be passed along to the consumer. Thus, the stakeholder quasi-tax burden combines with the normal tax burden already imposed by the social-welfare state on the consumer. The imposition of higher taxes is not likely to be seen as a disadvantage to the average stakeholder advocate, but it should serve as a warning signal to other citizens and business people.

As bureaucracy usually functions, untruths about the “responsibility of corporate leaders” cover the lie that there is no fiduciary responsibility to the corporate owners, the shareholders.

Finally, the adoption of a thoroughgoing stakeholder model would transform the corporation from its original situation of focusing on the simple matter of maximizing profits. It would have to focus on all the other stakeholder “investors” and their “claims” on the earnings of the corporation. It would become like a government agency, no longer worrying about the bottom line. It would only have to transfer any available funds to the diverse causes célèbre of stakeholders far and near. Becoming a government bureaucracy, it could not be expected to exhibit greater efficiency than the I.R.S. or the V.A. Its effect would be to lead the manager into pursuing his own stakeholder interests rather than the interests of the owners. It would reflect moral hazard on the part of the coached, socially conscious, indoctrinated manager who pursues his own interests rather than those of the owner.

For a more thorough and detailed treatment of these stakeholder issues, I invite the reader to see the much longer and completely documented exposition in two chapters of my book, Socialism.

Capitalism: Origins, Expansion, Decline, and the Attempted Revival in the United States.